I think of cinema as being primarily of a kind with the visual arts like painting, not with drama. It is, at base, moving pictures more so than filmed drama. We’re smack dab in the middle of imagery and representation where color and optical illusions sway the spectator the way eloquence and rhetoric sway the listener. . . . John Milius accomplishes what a film-maker tries to do – that is, he is able to draw the spectator into the world of images he created. Once we’re there into that world, we are then in a position to reflect upon the themes that undergird the movie, as you point out.
He goes on to explore this distinction in a bit more detail, culling out its implications for several different movies:
There is something lumpy and knotty about the esthetics in movies like Conan (1982) – and to that, I might add Excalibur (Boorman) and Dragonslayer (M.Robbins). Perhaps it was the state of the art of special effects at the time – close enough to imitating reality, but sufficiently imperfect so that the representation depends in part on our own imagination doing the rest to make a whole, convincing picture. It depends on our own input, too, not just passively taking in images. We’re thus more easily brought into the make-believe process that happens when watching a movie. . . . .the problem of special FX & cinematic/synthetic imagery technology today is that it does too much for us and winds up anesthetizing the images in the movieJames is onto something very interesting, in my view, and I'm very glad that he brought this focus on the aspect of spectacle (opsis) -- an aspect of Aristotelian aesthetics which I'd somewhat downplayed in my earlier piece, in favor of analyzing in terms of the triad of character, plot, and thought, why the older movie worked so well and why the new one, despite considerable technical investment and decent acting, seems fated to simply miss the mark. He continues:
I agree with the points you said on the three requisites drawn from Aristotle’s Poetics. The plot & characters were quite well developed. As were the thought-out themes which sustain the former two. I would thus just want to make the point that before we get to the discursive aspect of the film wherein these three get fleshed out, there is an initial process whereby the world of representations works on us. These visual representations are masterfully done by Milius & company and make the movie so memorable. He (or they) transports us there, we hear the dialogues, the soliloquys and “da lamentations of da women”, and are left (at least in my case) with a lot more than just swordplay and special effects.This seems dead-on to me, though I would also add that the earlier version of the film also excels in another key element or dimension of mimetic production -- music or soundtrack (melos) -- which equally supports, and arguably precedes, prepares the reception for plot, character, and thought. James' mention of the discourses also reminds me of a telling and parallel divergence in delivery or diction (lexis) between old and new. I'll delve into these in more detail shortly, but first, a last key point James makes:
[T]he big difference between Conan the Barbarian and Conan the Destroyer, aside from the fact that the latter simply sucked, was that the former painted a self-sufficient world. In terms of its place – the topos (or topia?) – it was u-topia, a nowhere – that plays up on its verisimilitude. It could have taken place…somewhere…a long time ago. Conan the Destroyer, on the other hand, took place on a Hollywood set. That was obvious.As I reread these passages, I'm reminded once again of the similar contrast between what to me has become the "classic" version of another film (or rather two films -- there's a whole story there), and a newer, remade, flattened, dulled version -- The Three/Four Musketeers
In my blog post earlier this year, in presenting the main dimensions through which Aristotle conceptualizes what goes on in drama, how it works or fails, and the criteria for evaluating a dramtic piece, I confined myself to discussing the three elements which Aristotle himself seems to regard as most essential, those deepest at the heart of dramatic production and performance. These are:
- Plot, or Story (mythos) -- what is going on in the piece, the over-arching narrative which binds or bonds all of the loose ends, the sub-plots, the private stories and perspectives, into some sort of unity -- a sequence of connected and (at least partly) intelligible actions
- Character -- or more properly, characterS, in the plural (ēthē -- the singular would be ēthos, not just the personalities of the dramatis personae, but their specifically moral characters, what kind of people they are or reveal themselves to be, down to their cores.
- Thought (dianoia) -- the views, the decisions, the reasonings and reflections of the characters, revealed in monologues, asides, speeches, dialogues, arguments, even taunts or jibes.
- Diction or Delivery (lexis) -- the style, the distinctive way of speaking, the choice of words, even, I'd argue, when one speaks and when one is -- dumbly or eloquently -- silent.
- Spectacle (opsis) -- what there is to be "seen," the look, along with all that synaesthetically accompanies that visual entanglement or offering, staging, arrangement, costume, scenery, and so on.
- Music or Soundtrack (melopoiia, melos) -- Aristotle actually has in mind the songs sung or chanted by the chorus, but there is no reason not to extend this further than his explicit intent in the Poetics to encompass that very key dimension of film.
That provides a good point to transition to reflecting on the teleological structure of drama and film, in particular genres like fantasy, science fiction, action, noir -- which exhibit interesting correspondences with the mythological and legendary narratives supplying material for classic epic and tragedy (even some comedy). I ought to warn that in writing of "teleological structure" here, I'm intentionally introducing an ambiguity between several different levels of the dramatic production. I'm also going to anachronistically shift language -- just for convenience's sake -- from this point on, no longer writing of "drama," but rather "film."
Teleology has to do with means and ends, orderings and evaluations, purposes and purposiveness, functions and activities. One -- or perhaps several -- levels of teleology are already involved or implicit within the film itself. Characters have motivations and desires, some of which they stick to, others suppress successfully or not, others sacrifice to higher or lower ends, and yet others perseveringly see through to the end. Certain of these will overlap, intersect with, or butt up against the trajectories mapped and followed out by other characters. This is part of what makes the plots, characters, thoughts -- the determinate matrix from which the film unfolds -- not only intelligible but interesting.
At a higher level, where the film is not the story and spectacle into which the viewer is absorbed, where we can ask about what is going on in the film, but where the film itself can be an object of consideration, we can ask the questions: What is the point, the purpose, the function of the film? to be sure, we can ask this of its parts, its portions, its passages, its fractions, transitions, continuities and back-references -- What is this action sequence doing? Why is this vignette in here? -- there is yet another level of teleological structure to the composition of wholes from parts. But we can ask about the overarching whole, the film itself: What is its purpose? What is it for? Asking and answering this is a necessary preliminary to making any useful judgements of value about film in general or about a film in particular -- and we always approach films with some answer in mind, even if one we unconsciously inherited, uncritically accepted, implicitly adopted.
So, what could the purposes or functions of film be? One might come up with a number of answers subordinating the film as an artistic production to some perceived good external to it -- making the film into a mere means to an extrinsic end. Films produced primarily for propaganda purposes would be of such a sort -- as would those engaged in merely to make money, or even those quickly cobbled out to fulfill some onerous contractual obligation.
What else? What other reasons exhibit a more intrinsic connection with the content and form of the film? Entertainment, providing pleasures perhaps mixed with or contrasted against pains of sorts, is certainly at the heart of all mimetic production. But, why are films pleasant? It's not simply because of what is depicted, in the sense of simple content which we enjoy. Rather, it's through the sorts of devices made possible through the complexity of plot, the interplay of characters through action, conflict, dialogue, revelation of who one is and what one things, alterations in perspective, allegiance, in understanding and commitment -- a number of which devices Aristotle analyses in the Poetics, "reversals" altering the condition of characters, for instance, or "recognitions" of what was previously unrealized, ongoing revelations unfolding character, "sufferings" deserved or undeserved, sequences of actions playing themselves out, and "complications" referencing events exceeding the immediately exhibited environment of the film and folding it into a world of meaning.
Aristotle very famously states as the first sentence of his Metaphysics
There is another dictum which, if I failed to acknowledge at this point, some reader would no doubt indignantly point out. In all this exploratory talk about the purpose of film, or dramatic production, however you want to call it, you are overlooking what Aristotle actually said, something we all know, if it is the only thing we know about his theory of drama. The purpose of tragedy -- and Conan can be seen in a sense as a sort of tragedy -- is catharsis, the intensification, outflow, expression, and "cleansing" of the emotions of the audience
It is true that evocation of emotions is centrally important, and Aristotle does accord pride of place -- at least if the number of mentions is a reliable index -- to fear and pity, by which the catharsis of emotion takes place. He also brings up another emotion for the audience is to be made to feel, philanthropia, "fellow-feeling," or perhaps partial identification or empathy with certain characters, sensing the relative justice and intensity of their own emotions, motives, responses. Anger is another emotion -- one intimately, even dangerously connected with a sense of justice or injustice in Aristotle's other works -- which he mentions specifically and provides counsel about in the Poetics.
The emotions are evoked and engaged in film -- and this can be done in simple, even simplistic ways, using well-worked-out old standby devices that can be confined to a single episode, and which might rely solely on action or spectacle or music -- but if the aim to to really involve the spectator capable of deeper, finer, more complex feelings, emotions and sentiments have to be associated in complex ways with the other more cognitive elements or dimensions -- and spectacle and music must intersect with, find their fuller significance in dialectical relationship with these other dimensions of plot, character, and thought, providing a simultaneously stark and rich sensory situatedness within -- and by which -- plot, character, thought play out. They must afford them grandeur, space, even what we might call leisure, so that emotion, action, thought, and structure can congeal into a greater unity. In great films, a kind of of non-didactic education is produced or better yet provoked, stimulating the play of desire in the audience, so that they ask all sorts of questions, with their eyes and ears and minds . . . and then what happened? Why did he do this? What did he choose between? How did he respond to that? What did he learn? What was the result? Did he give in or fall victim? Did he win?
. . . close enough to imitating reality, but sufficiently imperfect so that the representation depends in part on our own imagination doing the rest to make a whole, convincing picture.He's right, what's wanted is not the sort of wizardry that permits pure passivity, that fails to call for an effort of imagination. That's a condition for producing the part-world of the story, of the classic narrative, where a mythos can truly unroll, even grow.
I'm willing to grant James' point that before the more cognitively articulated elements of film can gain their hold upon us, spectacle has to transport us into that alternate imaginary realm -- but in the case of this film, I think that music rides flank to flank with spectacle from the start. And, I think the starkness, the spareness, the "lumpiness" of the visual aesthetic is actually mirrored in another key element which so far I've only mentioned -- lexis, the style, the diction, the way things are said in the movie, the modes in which thought, character, even moment of plot are expressed, particularly if we're willing to make an interpretative leap and unbind lexis from being confined to solely the articulation of language and extend it analogously to the articulation of action, of expression, and of silence as well as speech.
I don't want to stretch it so far that it covers everything. Music has its own distinctively different and equally resonant effects and structure. So does spectacle -- for instance the distinctively "knotty" and often spare scenery about which James writes. I do want to suggest, though, that the seriousness of the "self-sufficient world" conveyed or connoted by the film is in equally significant part a function of this lexis of deed and glance, of stance and gesture -- and that one prime characteristic of that lexis, not only on Conan's part, but on the part of a number of the other important characters, is a deliberateness, a willingness to scrutinize before talking.
There's a clear and prudent directorial choice not to fill what risks being empty time with words so that other modes of meaning, not only visual or musical but cognitive, desirous, intentional, emotional can emerge through silence -- particularly through the expressive, attentive silent moments of Conan himself. Similarly, the battle scenes might seem choreographically parsimonious, but when there's so few of them, each thrust, each parry, each slice, each maneuver for ground, each time an opponent sizes up another, it means something. Nothing gets lost in those older struggles. . . as, I must admit, even my attention does with the technical and technological virtuosity of the interminable, innovative, interchangeable and thus entirely boring fight scenes characteristic of today's movies.
Aristotle had insisted characters -- at least for tragedy and epic -- had to be great, not only in some moral sense, but in the sense of possessing and exhibiting the nobility able to provide the depth required for significant and gripping pathos on the part of an appreciative audience. That is present in Conan, a movie in which, among others, the question of "what is best in life?" is asked and answered, and by some characters even debated and reconsidered, a film not just about conflict and revenge, but about deliberation, sacrifice and even the value and nature of love and its counterfeits.
Wow. Much food for thought. Great post. I'm glad you found my comment of interest and help, too! For my own part, I hadn't taken into account music, and should have. Especially since I know well the movie's score by now!
ReplyDeleteSince we're talking cinema, I thought I'd mention another film that I recommend. It's rare that I ever come across anything akin to the movies mentioned above. But I did just that recently, to my delight. By chance I happened upon "Valhalla Rising" which can be viewed for free on youtube. Whereas "Tree of Life" evokes the couple nature/grace from the beginning, Valhalla Rising evokes nature/man. There are significant Christian themes (think Snake Plissken meets CS Lewis' Aslan), but the esthetics are somewhat different from Conan despite the seeming parallel between vikings & barbarians & swords, etc. The violence is gore, but done in such a way (I think - I dunno really since I closed my eyes during some parts of the action!), that it communicates something other than itself. Its not gratutious, its grotesque, I believe. In the preface to his play "Cromwell", Victor Hugo develops his notion of grotesque - for him, art strives for totality embracing not just beauty and the sublime, but also the ugly and deformed. The deformed, one-eyed viking (named "One-eye") is the vehicle by which man conquers nature by imitating the divine. (that's my interpretation, anyway).
As for Conan, I don't see this grotesque at play. I think this was a deliberate choice on Milius' part: other themes, other artistic tools deployed.
In any case. Fascinating discussion you started there!